Reduction and emergence in philosophy of mind: physicalism and the explanatory gap

Authors

  • J. Arturo Escobedo Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México
  • Miguel Angel Sebastian UNAM

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.22370/rhv2024iss25pp75-90

Keywords:

reductive explanation, a priori entailment, phenomenal consciousness, weak emergence, strong emergence

Abstract

Our conscious experiences seem to elude any explanation in scientific terms. They present paradigmatic case of reduction failure and they are the main motivation for postulating relations of emergence. Thus, various authors have pointed out that phenomenal properties must be something more than mere collections of physical properties. This leads to the rejection of physicalism. As a consequence, phenomenal properties either have to be added to the list of fundamental properties, or emerge from them. Alternatively, the physicalist must be able to explain how that failure in the explanation can be compatible with their position.

The aim of this paper is to clarify the concepts of reduction and emergence in the context of this debate in philosophy of mind, clearly distinguishing different types of epistemological relationships and their ontological consequences. This will allow us to have a better understanding of the commitments and the challenges different positions face.

References

Anderson, P. W. (1972). More is different. Broken symmetry and the nature of the hierarchical structure of science. Science, 177, 393-396. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.177.4047.393

Balog, K. (2009). Phenomenal concepts. En B. McLaughlin, A. Beckermann & S. Walter (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind (pp. 292-312). Oxford University Press.

Balog, K. (2012). In defense of the phenomenal concept strategy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84, 1-23. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2011.00541.x

Bedau, M. (1997). Weak emergence. En J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives: Mind, causation, and world (pp. 375-399). Blackwell.

Bedau, M. (2008). Is weak emergence just in the mind? Minds and Machines, 18, 443-459. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-008-9122-6

Block, N. (2006). Max Black’s objection to mind-body identity. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 2, 3-78.

Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford University Press.

Chalmers, D., & Jackson, F. (2001). Conceptual Analysis and Reductive Explanation. The Philosophical Review, 110(3), 315-360. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-110-3-315

Crutchfield, J. P., Doyne Farmer, J., Packard, N. H., & Shaw, R. S. (1986). Chaos. Scientific American, 255, 46-57.

Hempel, C. (1969). Reduction: ontological and linguistic facets. En P. S. Sidney & M. White (Eds.), Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in honor of Ernest Nagel. St. Martin’s Press.

Howell, R. (2007). The knowledge argument and objectivity. Philosophical Studies, 135(2), 145-177. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-007-9077-0

Howell, R. (2013). Consciousness and the limits of objectivity. Oxford University Press.

Humphreys, P. (1997). How Properties Emerge. Philosophy of Science, 64(1), 1-17. https://doi.org/10.1086/392533

Humphreys, P. (2015). More is different… Sometimes: Ising models, emergence and undecidability. En B. Falkenburg & M. Morrison (Eds.), Why more is different: philosophical issues in condensed matter physics and complex systems (pp. 137-152). Springer.

Heisenberg, W. (1927). Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik. Zeitschrift für Physik, 43(3-4), 172-198. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01397280

Humphreys, P. (2016). Emergence. Oxford University Press.

Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal Qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly, 32(127), 127-136. https://doi.org/10.2307/2960077

Levin, J. (2006). What is a phenomenal concept? En T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: new essays in consciousness and physicalism (pp. 87-110). Oxford University Press.

Levine, J. (1993). On leaving out what it’s like. En M. Davies & G. Humphreys (Eds.), Consciousness: psychological and philosophical essays (pp. 121-136). Blackwell.

Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 343-377. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048408312341131

Lewis, D. (1990). What experience teaches. En W. G. Lycan (Ed.), Mind and cognition (pp. 29-57). Blackwell.

Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Blackwell.

Nagel, T. (1974). What Is It Like to Be a Bat? The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435-450. https://doi.org/10.2307/2183914

Nemirow, L. (1990). Physicalism and the cognitive role of acquaintance. En W. G. Lycan (Ed.), Mind and cognition (pp. 490-499). Blackwell.

Papineau, D. (2006). Phenomenal and perceptual concepts. En T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: new essays in consciousness and physicalism (pp. 111-144). Oxford University Press.

Perry, J. (2001). Knowledge, possibility and consciousness. MIT Press.

Sebastián, M. Á. (2022a). El problema de la consciencia. Una introducción crítica a la discusión filosófica actual. Ediciones Cátedra.

Sebastián, M. Á. (2024). First-Person Perspective in Experience: Perspectival De Se Representation as an Explanation of the Delimitation Problem. Erkenntnis, 89(3), 947-969. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00564-4

Sebastián, M. Á. (manuscrito). Perspectival information and the knowledge argument. Reconsidering the first-person point of view.

Stanley, J., & Willlamson, T. (2001). Knowing How. Journal of Philosophy, 98(8), 411-444. https://doi.org/10.2307/2678403

Strogatz, S. (2001). Nonlinear Dynamics and Chaos: With Applications to Physics, Biology, Chemistry, and Engineering. Westview Press.

Published

2024-07-25

How to Cite

Escobedo, J. A., & Sebastian, M. A. (2024). Reduction and emergence in philosophy of mind: physicalism and the explanatory gap. Revista De Humanidades De Valparaíso, (25), 75–90. https://doi.org/10.22370/rhv2024iss25pp75-90

Issue

Section

Monographic Section